The units of evolution, paraphyly, etc.
Harvey E. Ballard, Jr.
hballard at STUDENTS.WISC.EDU
Mon Jun 16 11:25:26 CDT 1997
Genetic differentiation, involving genes, are ultimately responsible for=
phenotypic changes that result in the production of different species. But=
the degree of genetic differentiation differs dramatically among groups,=
and even among lineages within the same genus. Regarding the "unit of=
evolution", the vast majority of theoretical literature has reiterated for=
decades that the POPULATION is the unit of evolution. Indeed, it takes no=
great imagination to envision that individual populations within a larger=
collective that we may call a single species are capable of changing=
somewhat independently of other populations. Even the ability--not the=
theoretical capability but the actual physical phenomenon--of gene flow to=
occur to any significant extent among populations of a particular,=
widespread species has been called into question by some (I believe rightly=
so). More than a few studies have documented isolation--reproductive or=
other--limiting or precluding gene flow among different sets of populations=
that one could justifiably call species, but that show very little or NO=
observable genetic differentiation according to isozymes or chloroplast DNA=
data. Should these be subsumed into a single species just because our=
methods are too coarse or our sampling of genetic variation too cursory to=
detect genetic differentiation? I argue, no. In fact, I would argue that=
we should be taking the documented or interpreted presence of limitations=
to gene flow among populations within many groups as the result of some=
important genetic differentiation, whether or not we are capable of=
detecting differentiation with our methods; if we can, so much the better;=
if we can't, it doesn't change the existence of isolating barriers or=
limitations to gene flow that we can see, test or infer (regardless of what=
the populations do in the laboratory). I'll even be radical and argue that=
we should interpret genetic differentiation from the PLANT'S point of view,=
and ignore the source of genetic variation: in the case of taxa of hybrid=
origin, as with those of an origin by divergence, if the populations are=
predominantly isolated reproductively or ecologically, reproduce themselves=
effectively in nature, and exhibit a pattern of interpopulational and=
intrapopulational variation that suggests a different evolutionary=
trajectory that is independent of the parental taxa, I couldn't care less=
that the populations originated as de novo hybrids once upon a time (nor do=
the plants--it seems only systematists get their shorts in a bunch over the=
issue of whence the initial genetic variation arose).
How does this relate to the acceptance or rejection of paraphyly? Although=
comparatively few studies have yet been done examining multiple populations=
of particular species and several species in a particular complex (I'm=
thinking of plants here, for what that's worth), it's not infrequent in the=
literature to witness populations of a particular widespread species, using=
molecular phylogenetic data, that associate more closely with populations=
of other related species of more restricted distribution or somewhat=
different ecological preference than with populations of the same species. =
Indeed, one would expect to see evidence of this association of narrowly=
restricted species "embedded within" a series of populations of a=
widespread species IF different marginal populations of the widespread=
ancestral taxon gave rise to different geographically restricted related=
species (once geographical isolates of the ancestor). I would suggest that=
ANY progenitor-derivative event in which a smaller population with reduced=
genetic variability in comparison to the total ancestral population will=
result effectively in a monophyletic series of populations in the=
derivative and a paraphyletic series in the ancestral taxon (although some=
folks seem to circumvent this paradigm by saying that one cannot apply the=
terms "monophyletic" and "paraphyletic" to species). The further caveat=
that proponents of the genealogical phylogenetic species concept would=
make, if I understand the theoretical argument, is that the paraphyletic=
ancestral taxon would eventually become monophyletic, given enough time for=
gene flow to "tie together" the remnant populations assignable to the=
ancestor (or what it's now become). Extremists who accept only=
monophyletic taxa recommend not recognizing the paraphyletic taxon until it=
becomes demonstrably monophyletic. I would like to see more studies with=
multiple populations of individual species in species complexes of closely=
related taxa to find out whether or not there is in fact evidence for=
substantial gene flow uniting populations of widespread species. In a=
study of one of the more primitive species complexes in the genus Viola, in=
which ITS variation is sufficient to resolve even population-level=
variation, we have found that the widespread V. canadensis has several=
regional endemics embedded within it and that marginal populations of V.=
canadensis in the same region of each endemic generally associate with the=
endemics rather than "interior" populations of V. canadensis. If gene flow=
has not continued to the degree that it has "united" all populations of=
remaining V. canadensis following what is apparently a series of speciation=
events from geographical isolates in this relatively old (late Miocene?)=
species complex, how might we expect it to have proceeded in more recent=
groups? Doesn't this argue against the pragmatic applicability of a=
genealogical species concept or any other that refuses to accept=
paraphyletic species?
My problem with accepting only paraphyletic species involves three points.=
(1) A number of papers have recently suggested that an enormous number of=
paraphyletic species probably exist, in keeping with evolutionary=
hypotheses of certain speciation models. (2) We biologists worldwide, and=
individually, should be exerting much MORE effort to catalog and=
characterizing biodiversity from an alpha taxonomic standpoint before it=
slips from our grasps in the next few decades, and to leave taxa UNNAMED=
means to leave them uncharacterized--a suggestion that I find=
unconscionable and cowardly in the face of the biodiversity crisis=
assailing us. (3) Considering that organic evolution proceeds in a=
"non-monophyletic" fashion a goodly share of the time, systems of=
classification that refuse to recognize paraphyletic species reject a=
substantial proportion of the products of evolution and, in essence, create=
an "unnatural" classification system.
As some folks have suggested, here and elsewhere, the "compromise" that I=
argue for is separation of cladistic evaluations of relationships and=
patterns of differentiation from the process of characterization and=
categorization, at least at the species level where pragmatism and the=
products of population-level evolution will simply often be incongruent=
with the concept of monophyly. Interpreting the processes and products of=
evolution with hard data, and even "thinking like an evolving plant=
population", rather than behaving as a theoretician imposing hypothetical=
constructs onto the patterns of nature, would also help.
Boy, do I expect to be stepped on for that one!
Harvey Ballard
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
Harvey E. Ballard, Jr.
Postdoctoral Researcher, USDA-ARS, Potato Systematics Labs
1575 Horticulture, University of Wisconsin-Madison
Madison WI 53706
PHONE: (608) 262-0159; FAX: (608) 262-4743
and
Honorary Fellow, University of Wisconsin Herbarium
Botany Department
132 Birge, 430 Lincoln Drive
Madison WI 53706
PHONE: (608) 262-2792; FAX: (608) 262-7509
AFTER 31 JULY:
Assistant Professor
Department of Environmental and Plant Biology
Porter Hall
Ohio University
Athens OH 45701-2979
PHONE: (614) 593-1128; FAX: (614) 593-1130
E-MAIL [probably]: not yet known
More information about the Taxacom
mailing list